01 - Uniqueness of the Identity Element

Author

ChatGPT 4o

Published

May 18, 2025

Certainly. Below is a natural language version of the uniqueness of the identity element proof, tailored for a philosopher or mathematician who may not be familiar with the formal notation of algebra, but who appreciates rigorous reasoning and abstract structures.


đź§  Natural Language Proof: The Uniqueness of the Identity Element

Let us imagine a mathematical structure — call it a “group” — where we are allowed to combine things using some kind of operation. Think of this operation like a kind of abstract multiplication, or more generally, a rule for merging or transforming elements. We don’t need to know exactly what the elements are — they could be numbers, symmetries, moves in a puzzle, or anything — but we do assume that this merging behaves in a consistent and logical way.

In this setting, we are told that there exists a special kind of element, called the identity element. The defining feature of this element is that when you combine it with any other element — whether on the left or on the right — nothing happens. That is, the other element remains unchanged. It acts like a “do-nothing” or “neutral” element in the context of this operation.

Let’s say we have two different candidates for this neutral role. Call them e and e′. Our goal is to prove that, in fact, these two candidates must be the same — that is, that there cannot be two distinct identity elements in this system. There can be only one true identity.

Here is how we proceed:

  1. By the defining property of an identity, combining e with e′ (in that order) must leave e′ unchanged. Why? Because e is an identity, so it doesn’t affect anything it’s combined with.

    So we have:

    “Combining e with e′ gives just e′.”

  2. On the other hand, e′ is also supposed to be an identity. So if we reverse the order and combine e′ with e, that should also leave e unchanged.

    So we also have:

    “Combining e′ with e gives just e.”

Now, here’s the twist: we’re combining the same two elements, just in different orders. But because combining them one way gives e′, and the other way gives e, both combinations must result in the same thing (because that’s just basic logic — it’s the same two elements being combined). Therefore:

e = e′

So even if we suppose there are two different identity elements, logic forces them to be the same. Hence, in any such structure — any group — there can be only one identity element.


🎓 Philosophical Notes

  • This is an example of a proof by contradiction in disguise: we start by assuming two different things play the same role, and show that this assumption collapses — they must be one and the same.
  • The deeper takeaway is that the role of an identity in such a system is so constrained by its very definition that there is no room for multiplicity — any two identity candidates must behave identically with respect to all others and hence must be the same object.
  • This proof doesn’t rely on numbers or familiar operations. It applies equally to symmetries of space, logical operations, or compositional rules in language — anything where identity and combination are meaningful.

Would you like a similar treatment for the uniqueness of inverses? Or an analogy involving physical or metaphysical identity (e.g. â€śthe ship of Theseus meets group theory”)?

Group Axioms (First Principles)

A group \((G, \circ)\) is a set \(G\) with a binary operation \(\circ\) satisfying:

  1. Closure (G1):

    \[ \forall a, b \in G,\ a \circ b \in G \]

  2. Associativity (G2):

    \[ \forall a, b, c \in G,\ (a \circ b) \circ c = a \circ (b \circ c) \]

  3. Identity element exists (G3):

    \[ \exists e \in G \text{ such that } \forall g \in G,\ e \circ g = g \circ e = g \]

  4. Inverse element exists (G4):

    \[ \forall g \in G,\ \exists g^{-1} \in G \text{ such that } g \circ g^{-1} = g^{-1} \circ g = e \]

Now let’s unpack the identities used in the proof.


The Goal of the Proof

We are given:

  • \(e\) and \(e'\) are both identity elements.

We want to prove:

  • \(e = e'\)

Step-by-Step Justification of Each Equation

Equation (4.1):

\[ g \circ e = g = e \circ g,\ \forall g \in G \]

This is the definition of an identity element. This is justified directly by Axiom G3.


Equation (4.2):

\[ g \circ e' = g = e' \circ g,\ \forall g \in G \]

Same reasoning — since we suppose \(e'\) is also an identity element, this again comes by definition, i.e., by Axiom G3, applied to \(e'\).


Now the proof strategy: Plug specific values into these

We aim to relate \(e\) and \(e'\) by choosing specific elements for \(g\).

Equation (4.3):

\[ e' \circ e = e' \]

This is obtained by setting \(g = e'\) in equation (4.1), which is:

\[ g \circ e = g \Rightarrow e' \circ e = e' \]

This uses the fact that \(e\) is an identity (so this is G3 with \(g = e'\)).


Equation (4.4):

\[ e \circ e' = e \]

This is obtained by setting \(g = e\) in equation (4.2), i.e.:

\[ g \circ e' = g \Rightarrow e \circ e' = e \]

This uses the fact that \(e'\) is an identity (so again, G3 with \(g = e\)).


Combining These

Now we have:

  • From (4.3): \(e' = e' \circ e\)
  • From (4.4): \(e \circ e' = e\)

But we can also write:

  • \(e' = e' \circ e = e \circ e'\)

So both \(e\) and \(e'\) must be equal to \(e \circ e'\). Thus:

\[ e' = e \circ e' = e \Rightarrow e = e' \]

Therefore, the identity element is unique.


Summary

Each identity used in the proof is directly justified by applying Axiom G3 (the identity element axiom), to particular choices of elements in \(G\). The core idea is that if two elements both satisfy the identity property, then they must act identically when composed with each other — and this forces them to be equal.